Skip to main content
Humanities LibreTexts

1.4: Arguments

  • Page ID
    24659
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    When we give reasons for holding a view or reaching a conclusion, the process is intrinsically articulate. Giving reasons requires language, concepts and skill with words, not just a simple ability to talk. For two (or more) people to share their reasoning requires a kind of reflective articulateness, an ability to express reasoning in a way that is intelligible to a particular audience. . . . What we will call “argument” here is meant to capture everything we make explicit when we give reasons for a view or proposition. . . . Much of the difficulty in reasoning together comes from simply not understanding each other’s arguments—from not understanding the significance of the words to express reasons and the views they support.

    —LARRY WRIGHT1

    The Importance of Arguments

    I am in an unusual career, where arguments dominate my professional life. I am paid to teach my students what philosophers have had to say on a great array of topics. Almost always, these philosophers, whether they are the historical “biggies” or contemporary thinkers, support their theories with arguments. Obviously, if I am going to do my job, I need to help my students sort out the good arguments from the bad. As a professor, I also participate in what is called “shared governance,” and as a consequence, I am required to vote and help decide policies, curricula, and other matters of university importance. Administrators and my colleagues consistently defend positions of great significance to the institution with impassioned arguments. Since I take this part of my profession very seriously, I find it essential to decide which of these arguments I find most persuasive.

    Most of us are not simply consumers of arguments, we are producers as well. In my own professional work, I present and defend theories about privacy, the Constitution, the death penalty, the existence of God, and a number of other philosophically, politically, and legally controversial topics. As an active participant in shared governance, I take sides, advocate positions, and occasionally lead the charge for particular causes. All this demands that I defend my views. In these cases, it is my name on the argument, and there is a heightened sense not just of ownership but of personal and professional responsibility. I need my arguments to be as strong as they can be not just convincing but plausible and hopefully pointing in the right direction.

    Your life may not be as argument-intensive as mine, but if you stop to reflect a bit, I think you’ll find arguments all around you. Advertisers make arguments for why you should buy their products and politicians for why they deserve your vote. You may need the advice from accountants and economists, hopefully backed up with arguments, to plan for a major business investment or your retirement. And you are a producer of arguments as well. That memo you wrote to your boss for a change in the way things are done or the case you just made to your partner about the need to buy a new car is an argument.

    This book is about arguments and a suggested technique for distinguishing good arguments from bad ones. These general hints are intended to be of use both when you find yourself in the position of the consumer of an argument and when you must make some decision about the quality of its evidence as well as when you are the producer of the argument and desire to present the strongest evidence you can. I don’t claim to have a magic bullet that will automatically show the truth about complicated issues. But I think you will be pleasantly surprised at how often this technique proves useful for thinking through these issues, finding out where you stand, and even beginning the process of formulating your own arguments about them.

    What Is an Argument?

    One potentially misleading aspect in some of my previous examples is that when it comes to controversial issues such as abortion or the death penalty, tempers can be high. And trust me, debates about curriculum or university policy can be just as emotionally explosive. There is a perfectly fine use of the word argument that basically means a verbal fight. Joe and Sally got into a terrible argument about his failure to do his share of the house cleaning. That is not what we will mean by the term, however. Sure, there will be times when arguments are very important, and disagreements about their strength or weakness will touch our emotions as much as our reason. There will be many other times, however, when arguments are simply there for our consideration, and we can assess them free of any passion or personal commitment. Indeed, as much as is possible, I would recommend adopting the more dispassionate approach, even when you feel strongly about what is at issue.

    It is useful to see an argument as a complex arrangement of three quite different things. There will be what logicians call a conclusion—some theory, hypothesis, or position that the argument seeks to defend. There will be premises—facts, data, or evidence that the argument uses to support the conclusion. And there will be a relationship between the premises and conclusion whereby the conclusion follows from the premises. We can schematically represent an argument as follows:

    e1. Premise

    e2. Premise

    e3. Premise

    . . .

    en. Premise


    t0. Conclusion

    Let’s begin at the bottom. Every argument will have a conclusion—that’s part of the definition of an argument. When we put an argument in what we will be calling its schematic form, it will always come at the end, under the big, heavy line. But in the real world of arguments, we should treat the term conclusion as technical jargon. Conclusions don’t always come at the conclusion of a person’s argument. Sometimes they come at the beginning.

    Dick’s cheating on Jane. He told her he had to work late, but Sally saw his car at Joe’s Bar. Not only that, he leers at other women, and the last three times she called him, he didn’t answer.

    Sometimes they come in the middle.

    Charlie’s take-home exam was word-for-word identical to Sarah’s. Clearly, Charlie copied it from Sarah. The guy’s a loser, never comes to class, and doesn’t know how to write very well.

    And, of course, some of the time, they are at the end.

    The light from virtually every galaxy is “red-shifted.” This shows that every galaxy is moving away from every other galaxy. Therefore, the physical universe is expanding.

    I have used the lowercase letter t in my schematic representation to stand for theory. The subscript “0” is used to do two jobs. Although there is only one theory defended in the argument’s conclusion (though that single conclusion can be complicated and composed of many parts—“therefore, Jake did it or helped plan it, or someone read his diary”), we will need to keep track of other possible theories besides the one defended in the argument. So “0” can be understood as the number zero and starting a sequence of numbered theories. But the “0” can also be read as the letter o and standing for original—the original theory or conclusion in the argument.

    To standardize things, we will use the lowercase letter e to stand for an individual bit of evidence. There are no set numbers of premises, or pieces of the evidence, in an argument. Sometimes there will be just a single datum, and sometimes, there will be quite a bit of supporting data. The previous examples illustrate not just that conclusions can come in many places in the statement of an argument but that the same holds true the statements of the evidence.

    Let’s recast our schematized argument in terms of evidence for a theory:

    e1. Evidence (datum)

    e2. Evidence (another datum)

    e3. Evidence (another datum)

    . . .

    en. Evidence (another datum)


    t0. Theory

    Logical Connection

    We’ve said a bit about the top and the bottom in our schematic representation of an argument. What about that conspicuous, big, fat line? In good arguments, the conclusion follows from the premises; the evidence supports the theory. What exactly is this relationship of support or following from? That turns out to be a very controversial issue in both philosophy and mathematical logic.

    In some cases, the relationship is semantic. If we just understood enough about the meanings of all the words in the premises, we would see that the conclusion has to be true. Often the examples are pretty trivial.

    e1. The number is even.

    e2. The number is greater than seventeen.


    t0. The number is not prime.

    Other times, however, there’s quite a bit of information hiding in the premises, and the conclusions are a little surprising and quite significant.

    e1. The figure is a plane triangle.


    t0. The interior angles of the figure equal exactly 180°.

    Arguments of the previous type have a technical name. They are called deductive arguments. In a successful deductive argument, the relationship between the premises and conclusion (it’s artificial here to call them evidence and theory) is a very special one. Logicians call it validity. Valid arguments are ones where if the premises are true, the conclusion has to be true. Many colleges and universities have whole courses on deductive (or symbolic) logic. Very sophisticated techniques are developed for determining validity. We will not spend time reviewing this material because as interesting (and just plain fun) as it is, one almost never finds deductive arguments being put forward outside of academic philosophy and mathematics.

    A second way of connecting premises to conclusions relies on the technical fields of mathematics and statistics. We cannot as conveniently ignore these arguments, since they play huge roles in contemporary science. Our approach to them, however, will be a little indirect. Rather than going through the basics of probability theory and then developing statistical tests for making sense of numerical data, we will treat these arguments as special cases of inductive arguments. This latter jargon simply means that the argument claims that the conclusion follows from the premises but not deductively—that is, it is possible for the premises to be true, yet the conclusion turns out to be false. Now, of course, it should be relatively rare that in good inductive arguments, the premises would be true and the conclusion false; otherwise these arguments will not be very useful. It is a matter of great controversy in logic, philosophy, and even the sciences as to how we describe this relationship between evidence and theories. The rest of this book is devoted to showing you one way of characterizing this relationship.

    Inference to the Best Explanation

    Consider the three short examples mentioned previously. We had purported evidence that Dick was unfaithful—the leering, the excuse about being sick, the car outside the bar, and the missed phone calls. We had purported evidence about the copied take-home exam—the word-for-word identical submissions, Charlie’s chronic absences, and his failures as a writer. Finally, we had the evidence about the expanding universe—the red-shifted light from distant galaxies. In each of these cases, the suggested theory explains significant parts of our evidence. Charlie being a cheater doesn’t explain his bad writing, but it sure helps us understand how the two exams ended up being the same. Dick’s cheating (in a very different way) would explain why he was at the bar when he said he was sick. And an expanding universe explains the Doppler shift we observe in the light from galaxies.

    This suggests a generalization. Suppose we treat the theory being defended in an inductive argument as an explanation of the data (at least some of the data) contained in the evidence. We get the following very symmetrical picture of an argument:

    Behaviorism_1.gif
    Figure \(\PageIndex{1}\)

    Inference to the best explanation assumes this general picture of inductive arguments. The relationship of support or following from becomes one of good explanation. Evidence for a theory is strong, or good or sound, if and only if, the theory best explains the relevant data that is being offered as evidence. This definition of good evidence gives us a very useful device for testing the quality of purported evidence.

    In the next chapter, I intend to lay out a kind of practical test for answering questions about the strength of arguments, about the quality of evidence. Does Connie have good evidence that her boyfriend was smooching Mary Jane during his absence at the record hop? Is there a strong argument that Charlie copied the take-home exam? Do astronomers really know that the physical universe is expanding? We can only begin to answer these questions when we are in absolute agreement about what the argument is in the first place.

    A Couple of Arguments from Sherlock Holmes

    Let’s look at a couple of examples of evidence that lead to some conclusions for Sherlock Holmes.

    Here are the missing links of the very simple chain: 1. You had chalk between your left finger and thumb when you returned from the club last night. 2. You put chalk there when you play billiards, to steady the cue. 3. You never play billiards except with Thurston. 4. You told me, four weeks ago, that Thurston had an option on some South African property which would expire in a month, and which he desired you to share with him. 5. Your check book is locked in my drawer, and you have not asked for the key. 6. You do not propose to invest your money in this manner.2

    The beginning of The Adventure of the Dancing Men begins with a little case study in Sherlock Holmes’s “deductive” method. Holmes’s method, of course, is not deductive in the formal logician’s sense but inductive, or better, abductive. It is an inference to the best explanation. Holmes possesses a fair amount of data.

    e1. Watson had chalk between his left finger and thumb.

    e2. He uses the chalk when he plays billiards.

    e3. He only plays billiards with Thurston.

    e4. He told Holmes four weeks ago that Thurston had an option on some South African property, which would expire in a month.

    e5. Watson’s checkbook is locked in Holmes’s drawer.

    e6. Watson has not asked for the key.

    Holmes explains all this with the hypothesis that Watson has decided against the investment. Holmes goes on to explicate his reasoning with the metaphor of a chain.

    You see, my dear Watson . . . it is not really difficult to construct a series of inferences, each dependent on its predecessor and each simple in itself. If, after doing so, one simply knocks out all the central inferences and presents one’s audience with the starting-point and the conclusion, one may produce a startling, though possibly a meretricious, effect. Now, it was not really difficult, by an inspection of the groove between your left forefinger and thumb, to feel sure that you did not propose to invest your small capital in the gold fields.3

    Although I think it is clear that Holmes exaggerates when he claims that the inferences follow in sequential lockstep, the insight that explanatory reasoning often proceeds in steps is important. Here is how I would schematize Holmes’s inference.

    e1. Watson had chalk between his left finger and thumb.

    e2. He uses the chalk when he plays billiards.

    e3. He only plays billiards with Thurston.


    t′0. Watson played billiards with Thurston last night.

    e4. He told Holmes four weeks ago that Thurston had an option on some South African property, which would expire in a month.

    e5. Watson’s checkbook is locked in Holmes’s drawer.

    e6. Watson has not asked for the key.


    t″0. Watson has decided against the investment.

    Each of these inferences is to an “alleged” best explanation. t′0 explains the chalk on his hand and is consistent with Holmes’s background knowledge of Watson’s preferences in playing partners. t″0 explains the lack of a request for the key and is consistent with Holmes’s knowledge of what Watson told him four weeks ago and the location of the checkbook.

    But The Adventure of the Dancing Men is not really about chalk and South African investments; it’s ultimately about murder and a couple of other mysteries that lead to the murder and its solution.

    Behaviorism_1.gif
    Figure \(\PageIndex{2}\): Dancing men cypher

    Retrieved from Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, The Return of Sherlock Holmes, http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/108 (accessed June 26, 2018).

    You’ll enjoy the story, and it would be great practice if you paused here for a while and tried your hand at schematizing Holmes’s argument for what happened at Ridling Thorpe Manor.

    Consider, first, the mystery that gives the story its name. Holmes shows Watson a piece of paper with the above pencil markings.4

    This is our first piece of evidence.

    e1. The dancing men document

    Watson immediately offers an account: “Why, Holmes, it is a child’s drawing.” Holmes thinks otherwise. The dancing men drawings “have a meaning,” but they might be “arbitrary” (think “one if by land and two if by sea”) or they might be “systematic” (a cipher). Holmes bets on the latter. His client, Mr. Cubitt, has provided more data:

    e2. Mr. Cubitt’s wife, Elsie, received a letter from America that very much upset her.

    e3. Other dancing men inscriptions, on both paper and chalk applied to buildings, have turned up at Ridling Thorpe Manor.

    e4. Holmes has knowledge of the relative frequency of letters in the English language.


    t′0. The dancing men figures stand for letters. And the messages are in English.

    Holmes breaks the code. He is now able to translate the different messages that have turned up.

    This leads to the second mystery: Why is Elsie so reticent to tell her husband about her past? Why is she so upset and frightened by the dancing men messages? Why did she stop her husband from confronting the stranger they caught in the act of scrawling one of the messages? Holmes is in a position to answer many of these questions simply by decoding the messages he has. In addition, Holmes explains Elsie’s reticence and fear in terms of some connection to criminal activities in her past, and he knows that the correspondent is named Abe Slaney. A cable to a colleague in the States confirms that Slaney is “the most dangerous crook in Chicago.” Slaney is imploring Elsie to return to him and finally threatening her. Holmes and Watson have plenty of evidence that necessitates hurrying to the Norfolk countryside.

    e5. The contents of the messages

    e6. Slaney is the most dangerous crook in Chicago.

    e7. Slaney’s threat to Elsie


    t″0. Elsie, and perhaps Mr. Cubitt’s, lives are in danger.

    Sadly, they are too late. Immediately upon their arrival at the train station, they learn of the tragedy.

    “It’s a terrible business,” said the stationmaster. “They are shot, both Mr. Hilton Cubitt and his wife. She shot him and then herself—so the servants say. He’s dead and her life is despaired of.”5

    The stationmaster has, of course, not only introduced crucial new evidence but also offered an explanation. Holmes proceeds to the murder scene, interviews two servants, and examines the room where the bodies have been found.

    e8. Cubitt is shot dead, and Elsie is gravely wounded with a gunshot to the head.

    e9. A revolver is found, still containing four bullets.

    e10. The servants report several things:

    • • Both were awakened by the sound of a loud gunshot.
    • • A short while later, they heard a second shot.
    • • The victims were downstairs in the study.
    • • A strong smell of gun smoke in the study.
    • • The study window was shut and fastened.
    • • The house was locked from the inside, and no one could have left.
    • • They were both conscious of the smell of powder from the time they awakened upstairs.

    There are still several pages to go in The Adventures of the Dancing Men, but Holmes has now basically solved the case. His reasoning is classic inference to the best explanation (IBE). How and why did Mr. Cubitt and Elsie come to be shot? Why were the servants conscious of the smell of powder while upstairs? And what about the mysterious Slaney?

    Holmes is particularly fascinated by the powder aroma upstairs—“I commend that fact very carefully to your attention.”6 Holmes’s provisional hypothesis is that the window must have been open and the draft carried the smell. Careful examination of the study produces one last crucial bit of evidence.

    e11. A third bullet is discovered in the window sash.

    A third bullet! Someone else is involved! They examine outside the window and discover important new data.

    e12. Trampled flowers, large masculine footprints, and a spent cartridge

    But why only the sound of two gunshots? The first one was extremely loud. Might it “have been two shots fired almost at the same instant”?7 Holmes concludes “it was undoubtedly so.”8

    Holmes proceeds to entrap Slaney, and he confirms that he was one of the authors of the dancing men messages and that he and Mr. Cubitt exchanged gunshots through the window. The story never tells us precisely what happened to Elsie, but we know, just as Holmes knew.

    t0. Slaney sought to win Elsie back and was refused. He came to the manor and exchanged almost simultaneous gunshots with Cubitt. Elsie closed the window and either heartbroken at the death of her husband, guilt-ridden and feeling partial responsibility, or misguidedly seeking to preserve her husband’s good name, shot herself in the head.

    Schematizing the Argument

    Let me state something explicitly. The single hardest part of argument analysis or the IBE recipe may often be simply identifying what the argument is in the first place. There are a number of reasons for this. First and foremost, people aren’t always as clear as the might be when they state their arguments. But there are other complicating factors as well. My guess is that Conan Doyle would have said he wasn’t presenting an argument at all but simply telling a story. Still, I think it’s clear that the story is about Holmes’s following the evidence and coming to a conclusion about what happened. Add to all that some arguments touch on deeply divisive moral and political issues and few of us read them and set our personal politics to the side. These unavoidable biases that we all carry with us will often tempt us to simply misread what the argument is. Finally, as we get a hint of in this short story but becomes daunting when an argument is developed over the course of a whole book, the sheer number of words, thoughts, and sentences makes it extremely challenging to keep the structure of the argument clearly in mind.

    Granted all this, the first step in the IBE procedure that we will develop in the next chapter is not only the most difficult; it is the most important. If we misrepresent what the argument is, then all our work in analyzing it will be a waste of time. Who cares if you show “the argument” to be a spectacular success or a dismal failure if it wasn’t the real argument in the first place?

    Useful schematization requires three virtues, all of which defy simple characterization. First and foremost, as we have just emphasized, you should strive for copy fidelity. Your task is to characterize “the other person’s argument,” a representation of his or her evidence. You may think of better ways to make the argument, or you may even think that the evidence points in a different direction. That’s all fine and good and will be useful in later steps. Right now, however, your job is to faithfully represent the argument as it was stated. You want to also strive for brevity. We just saw how an argument might take up several pages of a short story but just imagine when we look in a later chapter at Darwin’s “abstract” of his theory in On the Origin of Species9 and try to keep straight all the evidence presented in more than four hundred pages. In order for your schematization to be useful to you, you will need to keep your representation of the evidence down to, say, no more than a page. Finally, and most difficult of all, you should strive for charity in your schematized arguments. You want to present the argument in the strongest form you can. This is not because you are being nice or discounting the previous virtue of copy fidelity. It is because you want to avoid at all costs weakening the evidence in the way you choose to schematize it. This is particularly important when you are dealing with arguments with which you disagree. If you come to the judgment that the evidence is weak, you need to make darn sure that you’ve given the evidence its best shot.

    Start at the Bottom (Find the Conclusion)

    We’ve already discussed the fact that conclusions may come anywhere in a statement of an argument. Still, in the schematic form I am urging on you, they always come at the bottom; they are always are identified as t0 (“0” to start a sequence of explanations and o as a reminder that this explanation is the original one), and they are always explanations of the data, not simply statements of the data. I strongly suggest that you begin your schematizing of the argument by trying to identify its conclusion.

    Oftentimes, you will find hints in the statement that will guide you to the argument’s conclusion. There are many words and phrases that are commonly used to alert readers or listeners that an inference is being drawn. Some of the classics you will find in any introductory logic book are as follows: “therefore,” “hence,” “so,” “it follows that,” and many others. But at other times, you are simply expected to pick out what the theory is that is supposed to be supported by the evidence. The best advice in these latter cases is simply to ask yourself something very general and vague such as “What’s the point of all this?” or, as suggested previously, “What the heck is going on?” Once you have a candidate, now see whether it explains some of the data in the argument. If it doesn’t seem to, you might want to look for another candidate as the argument’s conclusion.

    Two other general comments are appropriate here. First, don’t get discouraged. This is hard stuff. It will get easier and more natural as you get more experience using the recipe. And second, there will be times when you fail to discover a conclusion to begin your schematization because the passage of prose in front of you is not an argument in the first place. We obviously use language do lots of things—make simple assertions, push people’s buttons, or simply vent—stating an argument is only one use of language.

    Find the Relevant Evidence

    In The Adventure of the Dancing Men, we learned a lot of stuff. Holmes enjoyed playing with Watson’s head. Mr. Cubitt was “a tall, ruddy, clean shaven gentleman.” And that Inspector Martin was a “dapper little man, with a quick, alert manner and a waxed moustache.” This is just good literary technique. There’s also the important information at the end of the story when Slaney is arrested and confesses. But these data are only tangential to solving the murder. The data in e1 through e12, however, are crucial to understanding what happened, and all of it should be included in a complete schematization of the argument.

    Another Brokenhearted Teenager

    Here’s a sad story.

    Lyrics to “It’s My Party” can be found here: https://genius.com/Lesley-gore-its-my-party-lyrics, and Lesley Gore performing her song can be found here: https://youtu.be/acRMALrg1t4.

    Lesley is in tears, and she assures us we would be too if something similar happened to us. So what the heck happened? She doesn’t spell it out, but she knows and so do we. Take some time, now, and schematize Lesley’s argument. What is her evidence that Johnny is no longer hers and has taken up with Judy?

    EXERCISES

    1. 1. What is an argument? What are the three components of any argument?
    2. 2. How can you have a big argument, with lots of name-calling, without either party presenting an argument for why they feel aggrieved?
    3. 3. What do you think of the quality of Holmes’s evidence for his theory that Watson had decided not to go ahead with the investment? Why?

    QUIZ FOUR

    The following article comes from the New York Times. Your task is to schematize the argument for the conclusion that William Henry Harrison died from enteric fever. The article “What Really Killed William Henry Harrison?” by Jan McHugh and Philip A. Mackowiak, March 31, 2014, is available here: https://www.nytimes.com/2014/04/01/science/what-really-killed-william-henry-harrison.html

    Notes

    1. Larry Wright, Critical Thinking (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), ix.

    2. Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, “The Adventure of the Dancing Men,” in The Return of Sherlock Holmes (New York: W. R. Caldwell, 1905), http://www.gutenberg.org/files/108/108-h/108-h.htm.

    3. Doyle.

    4. Doyle.

    5. Doyle.

    6. Doyle.

    7. Doyle.

    8. Doyle.

    9. Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species: A Facsimile of the First Edition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).


    This page titled 1.4: Arguments is shared under a CC BY 4.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Jeffery L. Johnson (Portland State University Library) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.