Skip to main content
Humanities LibreTexts

17.3: The Representativeness Heuristic

  • Page ID
    95172
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    Mike is 6’2”, weighs over 200 lbs., (most of it muscle), lettered in two sports in college, and is highly aggressive. Which is more likely?

    1. Mike is a pro football player.
    2. Mike works in a bank.

    Here, we are given several details about Mike; the profile includes his size, build, record as an athlete, and aggressiveness. We are then asked about the relative frequency of people with this profile that are pro football players, compared to those with the profile who are bankers.

    What was your answer? There are almost certainly more bankers who fit the profile for the simple reason that there are so many more bankers than professional football players. We will return to this matter later in this chapter; the relevant point here is that Mike seems a lot more like our picture of a typical pro football player than like our typical picture of a banker. And this can lead us to conclude that he is more likely to be a pro football player.

    Many of us made just this sort of error with Linda. Linda, you may recall, is 31 years old, single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, and she participated in antinuclear demonstrations. Based on this description, you were asked whether it is more likely that Linda is (i) a bank teller or (ii) a bank teller who is active in the feminist movement. Although the former is more likely, many people commit the conjunction fallacy and conclude that the latter is more probable.

    What could lead to this mistake? Various factors probably play some role, but a major part of the story seems to be this. The description of Linda fits our profile (or stereotype) of someone active in today’s feminist movement. Linda strongly resembles (what we think of as) a typical or representative member of the movement. And because she resembles the typical or representative feminist, we think that she is very likely to be a feminist. Indeed, we may think this is so likely that we commit the conjunction fallacy.

    We use the representativeness heuristic when we conclude that the more like a representative or typical member of a category something is, the more likely it is to be a member of that category. Put in slightly different words, the likelihood that x is an A depends on the degree to which x resembles your typical A. We reason like this: x seems a lot like your typical A; therefore, x probably is an A.

    Sometimes this pattern of inference works, but it can also lead to very bad reasoning. For example, Linda resembles your typical feminist (or at least a stereotype of a typical feminist), so many of us conclude that she is likely to be a feminist. Mike resembles our picture of a pro football player, so many of us conclude that he probably is one. The cases differ because with Linda we go on to make a judgment about the probability of a conjunction, but with both Linda and Mike, we are misusing the representativeness heuristic.

    Overreliance on the representativeness heuristic may be one of the reasons why we are tempted to commit the gambler’s fallacy. You may believe that the outcomes of flips of a given coin are random; the outcomes of later flips aren’t influenced by those of earlier flips. Then you are asked whether sequence HTHHTHTT is more likely than HHHHTTTT. The first sequence may seem much more like our conception of a typical random outcome (one without any clear pattern), and so, we conclude that it is more likely. Here the representative heuristic leads us to judge things that strike us as representative or normal to be more likely than things that seem unusual.

    Specificity Revisited

    We have seen that the more detailed and specific a description of something is, the less likely that thing is to occur. The probability of a quarter’s landing heads is 1/2, the probability of its landing heads with Washington looking north is considerably less. But as a description becomes more specific, the thing described often becomes more concrete and easier to picture, and the added detail can make something seem more like our picture of a typical member of a given group.

    In Linda’s case, we add the claim that she is active in the feminist movement to the simple claim that she is a bank teller. The resulting profile resembles our conception of a typical feminist activist, and this can lead us to assume that she probably is a feminist activist. This may make it seem likely that she is a feminist activist. And this in turn makes it seem more likely that she is a bank teller and a feminist activist than that she is just a bank teller. But the very detail we add makes our claim, the conjunction, less probable than the simple claim that Linda is a bank teller.

    In short, if someone fits our profile (which may be just a crude stereotype) of the average, typical, or representative kidnapper, scrap-booker, or computer nerd, we are likely to weigh this fact more heavily than we should in estimating the probability that they are a kidnapper, scrap-booker, or computer nerd. This is fallacious, because in many cases there will be many people who fit the relevant profile who are not members of the group.


    This page titled 17.3: The Representativeness Heuristic is shared under a CC BY-NC 4.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Jason Southworth & Chris Swoyer via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.