Skip to main content
Humanities LibreTexts

1.6: New Data and Experimentation

  • Page ID
    24660
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    We must trust to nothing but facts: these are presented to us by nature and cannot deceive. We ought, in every instance, to submit our reasoning to the test of experiment, and never to search for truth but by the natural road of experiment and observation.

    —ANTOINE LAVOISIER1

    The Crazy Philosopher’s Evidence

    As you will remember, Johnson thought he had discovered evidence that there was a glitch in his iPod software. His schematized argument was as follows:

    e1. Johnson went to a Pink Martini concert, planning to ask for a specific encore.

    e2. “Que Sera Sera” was played during the concert.

    e3. He never got a chance to ask for “Lilly.”

    e4. On the ride home the next morning, he set his iPod to play all thirty-six of the Pink Martini songs.

    e5. He set the iPod to “Shuffle Songs.”

    e6. He listened to all thirty-six songs.

    e7. The last two songs played were “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera”—the imagined encore from the night before!

    e8. “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera” are the two Pink Martini songs he listens to most often.


    t0. There is a glitch in the iPod software—rather than playing the songs in completely “random” order, it is weighing things according to how often songs are listened to.

    There are thirty-six Pink Martini songs in Johnson’s iPod. What are the odds of his imagined encore occurring on the drive home? Let’s spend just a minute and figure that out. “Lilly” came up as the next to the last song played. The odds of this happening are straightforward. Any one of thirty-six songs could have come up here, so the odds are 1/36. But to have the encore, you had to also have “Que Sera Sera” come up last. So what are the odds of that happening? It’s actually easy to figure out. We already know the odds of “Lilly,” so it’s a question of “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera.” Since “Lilly” has already been played, the odds of “Que Sera Sera” are 1/35, and the odds of “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera” are 1/36 × 1/35, or 1/1,260. But of course, I would have also had my encore if the last two songs had been “Que Sera Sera” and then “Lilly.” The odds of this happening figure out exactly the same—1/1,260. So the odds of my encore popping up—“Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera” or “Que Sera Sera” and “Lilly” are 1/1,260 + 1/1,260, or 1/630.

    Certainly, one thing that would explain that 1/630 shot coming up on the ride home is that my imagined encore was composed of my two favorite (and most listened to) Pink Martini songs, and the program was illegitimately taking this into account in generating the “random” play order. But I hope it’s obvious by now, it’s easy enough to think of lots of rival explanations.

    t1. This was just a true, 1/630 coincidence.

    t2. This is not a software glitch; the iPod software is designed to do exactly this.

    t3. The iPod software is illegitimately weighing things, not by number of times played, but something else—length of the songs, where they occur in the album, and so on.

    t4. The philosopher set his iPod incorrectly.

    t5. The philosopher dozed in and out on the drive home and only thought that these two songs came up last.

    t6. The problem is in Johnson’s iPod—the hardware, not the software.

    My students have been worrying about what happened for the last several years on quizzes, ever since this really happened on a drive back from the Oregon League of Cities. They pretty generally rank the coincidence hypothesis as a much better explanation, though they are often surprised once they see the math that the odds are really 1/630. They also don’t seem to have too much confidence in their professor, since explanations such as t4 and t5 are consistently ranked ahead of t0. So according to the inference-to-the-best-explanation recipe, these students are committed to saying that Johnson’s evidence for the glitch theory is pretty weak.

    Why Don’t You Just Test It?

    I’ve told you this little anecdote for two very different reasons. One, of course, is I wanted a little exercise that would allow you to apply the inference-to-the-best-explanation test from chapter 5 to an argument. The other, though, is to tell you about a very common feature that my students have felt compelled to add to their discussions. There is almost a sense of frustration or least the need to lecture their professor. They suggest, indeed insist on, a very simple test of the glitch hypothesis.

    Look, isn’t there an obvious way to settle this matter? Turn off the iPod, reset everything, play Pink Martini’s songs again and see what happens. What is being proposed here is a classic little experiment—the kind of thing that some philosophers and scientists say is the defining condition of real science. I hope to convince you in the next couple of chapters that there is something brilliantly right about this claim but, at the same time, dangerously misleading.

    A Pretty Picture of Science

    Here is an idealization about the natural sciences. The scientist is really smart and is trained to go about her business in a very special, almost ritualized, way. She goes out and observes the world. Being smart and being trained to be a careful observer, she notices things. Sometimes she is puzzled by the things she observes and she asks questions, Why am I observing this? She starts looking for an explanation. Being smart and creative she thinks about this really hard and comes up with a possible answer—a hypothesis or a theory. This is all fine and good, but according to the pretty picture, it’s only now that the rules of science kick in. It’s not good enough to just have a theory; the theory must now be tested. The scientist must devise an experiment and let the results of the experiment determine the fate of her theory.

    Bear with me for a bit of technical stuff in symbolic logic. Logicians talk about conditionals, “if . . . then” sentences. There are two valid inferences that follow directly from a true conditional.

    1. 1. If the figure is a plane right triangle, then the interior angles total 180°.
    2. 2. The figure is a plane right triangle.

    1. 3. The interior angles total 180°.

    This inference is called modes ponens. A kind of mirror image inference is called modes tollens.

    1. 1. If the figure is a plane right triangle, then the interior angles total 180°.
    2. 2. The interior angles do not total 180°.

    1. 3. The figure is not a plane right triangle.

    Finally, there is a tempting inference that is not valid but is rather a logical fallacy, affirming the consequent.

    1. 1. If the figure is a plane right triangle, then the interior angles total 180º.
    2. 2. The interior angles total 180º.

    1. 3. The figure is a plane right triangle.

    You can easily spot the fallacy by noting that the figure might total 180° because it’s a triangle, but, at the same time, not be a right triangle but rather, say, an equilateral triangle.

    OK, so what does all this have to do with the pretty picture of science and maybe Johnson’s iPod? Well, suppose the conditional sets up something we might expect to see in an experimental circumstance, given the theory we are testing is true.

    1. 1. If the theory is true, we will see . . . in the experiment.

    By the inference of modes tollens, we will be able to falsify the theory by disconfirming it in an experiment.

    1. 1. If the theory is true, we will see . . . in the experiment.
    2. 2. We do not see . . . in the experiment.

    1. 3. The theory is not true.

    Experiments, according to the pretty picture, provide tests that can show us that theories are false. They cannot, however, show us that theories are true. Remember, it is a fallacy to affirm the consequent.

    1. 1. If the theory is true, we will see . . . in the experiment.
    2. 2. We see . . . in the experiment.

    1. 3. The theory is true.

    A Better, But Untidy, Picture of Scientific Disconfirmation

    Now, the theory about the iPod hardly counts as deeply scientific, but suppose we imagine an experiment nonetheless. The conditional that sets all this up looks something such as the following:

    1. 1. If there is a glitch in the software, so that when the iPod is set to play all the songs by an artist and is set to “shuffle” these songs, then rather than playing them in random order, it will play the most often listened to tracks last.

    I could test my theory by reprogramming everything with the Pink Martini tracks, but since I’ve offered a general theory, let’s test it with a different artist. I have lots of Lucinda Williams’s albums, and I’m certain I listen to two of her songs, “Right in Time” and “Essence,” the most. So if I set my iPod to play all her tracks and to shuffle them, I am predicting that the two songs will be played last.

    Suppose I do all this with my iPod and listen to all her songs—more than a hundred, I’d say. We can imagine four different outcomes to the experiment. Focusing on the last two songs, we might observe any of the following.

    ena. The two songs come up as the last two played.

    enb. Neither song is in the last two.

    enc. Only “Right in Time” is in the last two.

    end. Only “Essence” is in the last two.

    Options enc and end are interesting and deserve further study, but let’s set them to the side and focus on the “pure” experimental outcomes. According to the pretty picture, enb conclusively establishes that the glitch theory is false. But isn’t that a little extreme? We’ve already honed our skills at rival explanations—surely we can imagine scenarios where the glitch hypothesis is (was) true but neither song played last.

    t1. Between the drive home and the experiment, iTunes downloaded a newer (debugged) version of the software.

    t2. The glitch only occurs in playlists shorter than fifty songs.

    t3. There is a countervailing glitch when any of the songs are classified as “country.”

    It’s doubtful in the extreme that a negative experimental outcome can falsify a theory, though it certainly can provide strong evidence that there is something wrong with the theory.

    The problem here goes back to the original conditional that set up the experiment in the first place. Remember the difference between a sound argument and a valid one? The if . . . then sentence that gets our inference going in the first place states an absolute connection between the glitch theory and the predicted outcome of the experiment. But the rival explanations we have just considered above seem to show that this connection is not so absolute after all. Almost always the conditional that sets up our experiment contains what Larry Wright calls a weasel word. A more modest, but also more accurate, statement of the predicted experimental outcome will look more like this:

    If the theory in question is true, then all things being equal we will see . . . in our experiment.

    We predict that we will observe an as-yet-undiscovered planet at such-and-such location in the night sky, but certainly not if the observatory is socked in by clouds. We expect the solution to turn a certain color in our chemistry experiment but not if the test tube is contaminated.

    When we include this suppressed, but understood, ceteris paribus clause,2 our inference looks a little more problematic.

    1. 1. If there is a glitch in the software, so that when the iPod is set to play all the songs by an artist and is set to “shuffle” these songs, then, all things being equal, rather than playing them in random order, it will play the most often listened to tracks last.
    2. 2. “Essence” and “Right in Time” did not play last.

    Two valid conclusions can be derived from these premises. One, of course, is that the glitch hypothesis is mistaken. But as a matter of pure logic, it is equally legitimate to infer that all things in our experimental circumstances were not equal.

    Does any of this mean that the “scientific method” and the requirement that we experimentally test our theories is a waste of time? Nothing could be further from the truth. Let’s go back to our original “evidence” for the glitch theory but add to it the new data from our experiment.

    e1. Johnson went to a Pink Martini concert, planning to ask for a specific encore.

    e2. “Que Sera Sera” was played during the concert.

    e3. He never got a chance to ask for “Lilly.”

    e4. On the ride home the next morning, he set his iPod to play all thirty-six of the Pink Martini songs.

    e5. He set the iPod to “Shuffle Songs.”

    e6. He listened to all thirty-six songs.

    e7. The last two songs played were “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera”—the imagined encore from the night before!

    e8. “Lilly” and “Que Sera Sera” are the two Pink Martini songs he listens to most often.

    e9. When Johnson tried the “shuffle all songs” routine for Lucinda Williams, his most listened to songs did not come up last.


    t0. There is a glitch in the iPod software—rather than playing the songs in completely “random” order, it is weighing things according to how often songs are listened to.

    We’ve already imagined some rivals to e9, but I assume that you would all agree with me that t0 has been seriously weakened by our experiment and that the random fluke hypothesis or the operator error rivals look even better.

    The moral here is straightforward. When a theory suggests that we can expect to see something as yet undiscovered and we go out and look for this thing but don’t find it, this is highly relevant new data that almost always hurts the status of the original explanation as being the best explanation of everything, including, of course, the experimental results.

    A Better, But Untidy, Picture of Scientific Confirmation

    None of what I have just told you is earthshaking nor is it unknown by careful scientists and philosophers. Still, the pretty picture, partly because it is so pretty, can allow us to lose sight of the subtleties of experimental design and protocol. Maybe even more problematic for the pretty picture is the evidential value of experimental confirmation.

    Suppose I program my iPod to play all 116 Lucinda Williams tracks. I set the iPod to shuffle the songs and then sit back for a really long time and wait to see what the last two songs are. Sure enough, up pops “Essence” and “Right in Time” as the last two played. What do you think of my glitch hypothesis now?

    According to the pretty picture, my theory has been put to the test and perhaps surprisingly, has survived the test. But it would be the fallacy of affirming the consequent to say that the experiment has confirmed my theory. We’ve already seen that if confirmation means “logically derived” from the experimental setup and results, that’s exactly right. But none of this means that the experiment hasn’t produced very strong evidence that the songs are not playing in purely random order.3

    What is the best explanation of e1 through e8 when we add the positive experimental result below?

    e9. When Johnson tried the “shuffle all songs” routine for Lucinda Williams, his most listened to songs did indeed come up last.

    All the rivals we thought of with Pink Martini are still possible, but hardly any seem plausible any longer. One of the most seriously misleading features of the pretty picture is that it sets up an asymmetry between experimental confirmation and disconfirmation. We’ve seen why as a matter of deductive logic this asymmetry exists. But no such asymmetry exists when we see experimental results as additional data that the tested theory and its rivals must explain.

    The Significance of New Data

    One of the remarkable things about the natural sciences is that we can devise experiments and go looking for highly relevant new data. But new data can cause us to rethink our evidence or feel even more confident about it in any of the arguments we’ve been thinking about, not just the scientific ones. If we find out that Dick’s been in the hospital with pneumonia and that he loaned his car to his buddy, Sam, things are going to seem much more promising for Dick and Jane. And if we find a copy of Sarah’s midterm on Charlie’s laptop, the case for cheating is obviously strengthened.

    Three very important things follow from all this. The first is that evidence evaluation is always relative to what we presently know. If we learn new things and assemble them in new arguments, there will be times when our original conclusion will be strengthened, times when it will be weakened, and times when it will be pretty much left untouched. The second is that new data are always possible. The fact that we could imagine rival explanations means that we can imagine new evidence for these rivals. But this last fact leads to our third moral. Just because new data are possible, it does not mean that our assessment of the current evidence is unreliable. If all the rivals are farfetched, then the chances of finding new data that supports them are pretty slim. We do, of course, need a certain kind of intellectual modesty. We concede that things could change on the basis of new discoveries. But at the same time, for some kinds of evidence, we can be pretty confident that they won’t change.

    EXERCISES

    1. 1. According to the “pretty picture of science,” why is it possible to disconfirm a scientific theory but never confirm one?
    2. 2. What kind of new data would strengthen Connie’s evidence about what happened at the record hop? What kind of new data would weaken her theory?

    QUIZ SIX

    For the past few years, I have been forming an uncharitable hypothesis about one of my colleagues. He is Professor Hide-Smith-Jones, who teaches in the Department of Hermeneutic Metaphysics. I believe that he virtually gives away grades and demands almost no work from his students. His courses are wildly popular with students and have very high enrollments. What started my suspicions was a number of students who complained about the workload in my courses, who I later discovered were all hermeneutic metaphysics majors. A couple of my online students explicitly compared my course to Hide-Smith-Jones’s courses, accusing me of being unfair and unreasonable. This past weekend, I went into the university’s database and looked at the transcripts for all my advisees in the past five years. Many of them had taken at least one course with Hide-Smith-Jones. I discovered that on average, the grades they earned in his courses were .78 grade points higher than their total grade point averages.

    1. 1. Use the tools of inference to the best explanation to assess the quality evidence we have for Johnson’s theory that Hide-Smith-Jones is an easy grader who doesn’t demand much from his students.
    2. 2. Explain a test or experiment that could be conducted to test Johnson’s hypothesis.
    3. 3. Using inference to the best explanation, show how new data could be discovered that would either help (confirm) or hurt (disconfirm) Johnson’s theory.

    Notes

    1. Antoine Lavoisier, Elements of Chemistry, trans. Robert Kerr (Edinburgh, Scotland: Dover, 1790), xiii–xvii, www.iupui.edu/~histwhs/H374.dir/H374.webreader/Lavoisier.elements.html.

    2. The online Merriam-Webster Dictionary defines ceteris paribus as “if all other relevant things, factors, or elements remain unaltered.”

    3. It is, of course, true that devices such as iPods do not truly generate anything randomly. But their random number generating algorithms simulate randomness for all practical purposes.


    This page titled 1.6: New Data and Experimentation is shared under a CC BY 4.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Jeffery L. Johnson (Portland State University Library) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.