3.2: Nature's Helping Hand
- Page ID
- 26300
\( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)
\( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)
\( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)
( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)
\( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)
\( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)
\( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\)
\( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)
\( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\)
\( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)
\( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\)
\( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)
\( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\)
\( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)
\( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\)
\( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)
\( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\)
\( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)
\( \newcommand{\vectorA}[1]{\vec{#1}} % arrow\)
\( \newcommand{\vectorAt}[1]{\vec{\text{#1}}} % arrow\)
\( \newcommand{\vectorB}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)
\( \newcommand{\vectorC}[1]{\textbf{#1}} \)
\( \newcommand{\vectorD}[1]{\overrightarrow{#1}} \)
\( \newcommand{\vectorDt}[1]{\overrightarrow{\text{#1}}} \)
\( \newcommand{\vectE}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash{\mathbf {#1}}}} \)
\( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)
\( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)
\(\newcommand{\avec}{\mathbf a}\) \(\newcommand{\bvec}{\mathbf b}\) \(\newcommand{\cvec}{\mathbf c}\) \(\newcommand{\dvec}{\mathbf d}\) \(\newcommand{\dtil}{\widetilde{\mathbf d}}\) \(\newcommand{\evec}{\mathbf e}\) \(\newcommand{\fvec}{\mathbf f}\) \(\newcommand{\nvec}{\mathbf n}\) \(\newcommand{\pvec}{\mathbf p}\) \(\newcommand{\qvec}{\mathbf q}\) \(\newcommand{\svec}{\mathbf s}\) \(\newcommand{\tvec}{\mathbf t}\) \(\newcommand{\uvec}{\mathbf u}\) \(\newcommand{\vvec}{\mathbf v}\) \(\newcommand{\wvec}{\mathbf w}\) \(\newcommand{\xvec}{\mathbf x}\) \(\newcommand{\yvec}{\mathbf y}\) \(\newcommand{\zvec}{\mathbf z}\) \(\newcommand{\rvec}{\mathbf r}\) \(\newcommand{\mvec}{\mathbf m}\) \(\newcommand{\zerovec}{\mathbf 0}\) \(\newcommand{\onevec}{\mathbf 1}\) \(\newcommand{\real}{\mathbb R}\) \(\newcommand{\twovec}[2]{\left[\begin{array}{r}#1 \\ #2 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\ctwovec}[2]{\left[\begin{array}{c}#1 \\ #2 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\threevec}[3]{\left[\begin{array}{r}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\cthreevec}[3]{\left[\begin{array}{c}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\fourvec}[4]{\left[\begin{array}{r}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \\ #4 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\cfourvec}[4]{\left[\begin{array}{c}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \\ #4 \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\fivevec}[5]{\left[\begin{array}{r}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \\ #4 \\ #5 \\ \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\cfivevec}[5]{\left[\begin{array}{c}#1 \\ #2 \\ #3 \\ #4 \\ #5 \\ \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\mattwo}[4]{\left[\begin{array}{rr}#1 \amp #2 \\ #3 \amp #4 \\ \end{array}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\laspan}[1]{\text{Span}\{#1\}}\) \(\newcommand{\bcal}{\cal B}\) \(\newcommand{\ccal}{\cal C}\) \(\newcommand{\scal}{\cal S}\) \(\newcommand{\wcal}{\cal W}\) \(\newcommand{\ecal}{\cal E}\) \(\newcommand{\coords}[2]{\left\{#1\right\}_{#2}}\) \(\newcommand{\gray}[1]{\color{gray}{#1}}\) \(\newcommand{\lgray}[1]{\color{lightgray}{#1}}\) \(\newcommand{\rank}{\operatorname{rank}}\) \(\newcommand{\row}{\text{Row}}\) \(\newcommand{\col}{\text{Col}}\) \(\renewcommand{\row}{\text{Row}}\) \(\newcommand{\nul}{\text{Nul}}\) \(\newcommand{\var}{\text{Var}}\) \(\newcommand{\corr}{\text{corr}}\) \(\newcommand{\len}[1]{\left|#1\right|}\) \(\newcommand{\bbar}{\overline{\bvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\bhat}{\widehat{\bvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\bperp}{\bvec^\perp}\) \(\newcommand{\xhat}{\widehat{\xvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\vhat}{\widehat{\vvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\uhat}{\widehat{\uvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\what}{\widehat{\wvec}}\) \(\newcommand{\Sighat}{\widehat{\Sigma}}\) \(\newcommand{\lt}{<}\) \(\newcommand{\gt}{>}\) \(\newcommand{\amp}{&}\) \(\definecolor{fillinmathshade}{gray}{0.9}\)Cooperation between Builder and Nature as a Rhetorical Strategy in Vitruvius, Statius and Pliny the Younger
Bettina Reitz
Introduction
The achievements of engineers are one of the things which we today associate most readily with Roman civilisation. The building of roads and bridges, the construction of aqueducts, the digging of huge tunnels, clearance of mountain passes, construction of vast palaces – what could be more Roman? However, in antiquity no less than today, such massive engineering projects and alterations of the natural landscape were not only appreciated and admired, but also criticised and condemned. In this paper, I aim neither at an ecological assessment of the impact of Roman civilisation, nor a reconstruction of Roman environmental attitudes from contemporary literary sources [1]. Rather, I would like to consider how literary texts describe interventions in nature, and how these descriptions are designed to steer our evaluation of such projects.
In analysing ancient texts which evaluate manipulations of nature, we need to be aware that condemnation or approval of any instance of engineering or construction does not depend on the kind or scale of the activity itself. Rather, the kind of text and the context of the evaluation determine whether the positive or the negative sides of such an intervention are activated. Any engineering event can potentially be cast in a positive or a negative light. Roman authors need to negotiate this ambivalence inherent in the theme of intervention in nature. But what specific strategies do they employ in order to convince readers either of the virtues or the dangers of such activity? The strategies most widely used in Roman texts are to stress public usefulness on the one hand and private luxury on the other. For example, a text describing the building of a new aqueduct could make this project look like the hallmark of a good ruler by emphasising that the aqueduct was intended to supply the city with clean water. If, on the other hand, the description implied that the aqueduct was intended to supply the builder’s own gardens with water, the construction appears an act of wanton luxury [2]. This paper deals with a less common rhetorical strategy, employed by authors for the purpose of suppressing the potentially immoral connotations of altering nature on a grand scale.
The Rhetoric of War with Nature
When Roman authors describe large-scale alterations of nature or the landscape, they often increase the drama and vividness of their descriptions by (more or less explicitly) personifying nature, so that she can react to the act of alteration. In the majority of instances, nature is portrayed as resisting the interventions. The builder, therefore, has to overcome this resistance through a struggle and coerce nature into submission.
This rhetoric of struggle and victory can be used both positively and negatively in the debate about the moral implications of engineering. Nature’s unwillingness to cooperate can be one way of highlighting the transgressive and immoral nature of the enterprise [3]. However, more commonly, the rhetoric of fight and victory over nature can serve the purpose of those authors wanting to praise the achievement: emphasizing nature’s resistance can add to the prestige of the victorious engineer, who celebrates a triumph over nature subdued.
One example of such a rhetorical use of the metaphors of war and victory is Domitian’s triumphal victory over the river Volturnus in Statius’ Silvae 4.3, a poem about the construction of the Via Domitiana [4]. In this poem, the river god Volturnus himself rises from the depths, and, leaning against the newly-built bridge, thanks the emperor Domitian for ordering and taming him and turning him into a clean and channeled stream (Silvae 4.3.72-84):
“Kind orderer of my plains, who bound me in the law of a straight channel when I spread over distant valleys nor knew to keep within my banks, see, now I, the turbulent bully, that in time past barely tolerated imperiled barks, I bear a bridge and am trampled by crossing feet. I that was wont to carry off the land and whirl woods (ah shame!) begin to be a river. But I give you thanks and my servitude is worthwhile because I have yielded under your guidance at your command, and because you shall be read of as supreme ruler and conqueror of my bank.” (translation: Shackleton Bailey, adapted) [5]
The eventual acquiescence of the river has been achieved, as the martial metaphors show, only by a struggle in which man has triumphed over river. The river god speaks of himself in the language of a slave taken in war: the river is bound (ligasti 75), suffers servitude (servitus 80), while the builder is in command and gives orders (te duce, te iubente 81) [6]. Of course, there is the question of whether to read this ‘straight’, as an exuberant praise poem for the emperor [7]. Some have rather interpreted the rhetoric of war and violence as working the other way and suggested that the enslavement of the river, now trampled underfoot, is supposed to evoke the reader’s unease [8]. However we choose to read Statius’ provocative praise, it should be noted that this kind of martial language is a very common way of representing human involvement with nature [9].
Natural Cooperation
I would now like to consider a selection of passages which, exceptionally, show nature not as resisting (the ‘default’ situation) but as willingly cooperating with the builder. These cases are comparatively rare because this cooperative stance of nature lightens the work of the builder and therefore makes it appear less of an achievement. However, this rhetoric of cooperation has the advantage of rendering the alteration of nature a morally less ambivalent process. In order to downplay the dangerous sides of construction, the author turns nature into a partner who cooperates with the enterprising builder. This strategy potentially lessens the achievement of the builder, but it also makes his work morally unexceptionable.
In this article, I consider three instances of this strategy at work. I begin with Vitruvius, the first century BCE author of the De Architectura. One of the fundamental principles underlying his entire work is the cooperation between architect and nature, and I focus on one programmatic passage where this general principle is formulated. I then discuss two instances where the moral legitimacy of specific alterations of nature is at stake: firstly, the earliest of the villa poems in Statius’ Silvae, and secondly, the elder Pliny’s chapters on the use of marble.
Vitruvius’ De Architectura and the Ideal Architect
In the De Architectura, building is described as a natural process, which mirrors in its different aspects processes found in nature. An ideal of harmony between nature and the architect underlies Vitruvius’ entire work [10]. In the preface to book 2, Vitruvius expresses the ideal of cooperation between architecture and nature by means of an introductory anecdote [11]. While Alexander the Great was engaged in holding court and dispensing justice, an architect, Dinocrates, dressed himself up in the clothes and attributes of Hercules and approached the king. When asked what he wanted, he told the king (2 praef. 2):
He replied: “I am Dinocrates, a Macedonian architect, who brings you ideas and plans worthy of your distinction. For I have moulded Mount Athos into the shape of the statue of a man, in whose left hand I have shown the ramparts of a very extensive city, in his right a bowl to receive the water of all the rivers which are in that mountain, so that they will flow thence into the sea.” (translation: F. Granger, adapted) [12]
Alexander is pleased with this plan, but he does ask the architect whether the city designed in this way could easily be supplied with agricultural produce:
Alexander, delighted with this conception, at once inquired if there were fields round about which could furnish that city with a corn supply. When he found this could not be done, except by sea transport, he said: “I note, Dinocrates, the unusual formation of your plan, and am pleased with it, but I perceive that if anyone were to establish a colony in that place, his judgment would be blamed. For just as a child when born, if it lacks the nurse’s milk cannot be fed, nor led up the stairway of growing life, so a city without cornfields and their produce abounding within its ramparts, cannot grow, nor become populous without abundance of food, nor maintain its people without a supply. Therefore, just as I think your planning worthy of approval, so, in my judgment, the site is worthy of disapproval …” (translation: F. Granger, adapted) [13]
Alexander himself then discovers a more suitable location for the foundation of a great city, equipped with a natural harbour and surrounded by fertile lands, and Dinocrates receives the commission of laying out a city in this spot: Alexandria (2 praef. 4).
I read this episode as a programmatic statement of Vitruvius’ attitude to architecture in relation to nature. In Vitruvian thought, architecture ideally develops organically out of nature, respects natural conditions and works in harmony with them. In this anecdote, the architect Dinocrates does not initially take this fundamental ‘philosophy of architecture’ into account. It is significant that Alexander’s reason for his refusal in the Vitruvian version of the story differs from other known versions. In the most extensive version of the anecdote apart from Vitruvius’ own, Plutarch has Alexander refuse because Athos already bears witness to the arrogance of another ruler, the Persian king Xerxes [14].
In Vitruvius’ version, Alexander’s refusal has nothing to do with his fear of hybristic or tyrannical behaviour. His refusal is also not motivated solely by economic motives. A larger ideal lies behind Alexander’s desire to let human ingenuity be combined with natural suitability. Nature and architecture have to work together to achieve results (in this case, the megalopolis par excellence, Alexandria). Admittedly, there is a certain imbalance in this cooperative relationship. For the most part, the architect has to adapt to what nature provides. However, nature is also represented as taking an active part in the process: she has to support the foundation of the city by providing produce, just as the nurse, in Alexander’s simile, has to feed the child to allow it to grow [15].
Another difference between the Vitruvian version and the legend as it is told by Plutarch is also instructive. In Plutarch, the architect describes the site of Mount Athos as naturally suitable to such a project: the formation of the rock apparently already suggests the human form [16]. Tellingly, this detail does not feature in Vitruvius’ account, where Dinocrates plans to shape Athos so himself, not adapt what already exists [17]. Vitruvius’ point is precisely that the Athos-plan does not rely on the cooperation of nature, and is therefore inferior to the Alexandria-plan, where nature supports the foundation of a city and offers the architect fertile land and a natural harbour.
The programmatic statement exemplified by this anecdote is that the basis of (good) architecture has to be cooperation between man and nature. Architecture has to adapt to what nature offers and proceed in accordance with her laws. Nature, on the other hand, often lends the architect a hand in achieving his designs – provided he accepts the offered hand. To bring home the point, the Dinocrates-episode is immediately followed by another, equally important, programmatic passage: Vitruvius’ description of the development of culture, and especially architecture, from its earliest beginnings. Here, too, architecture develops harmoniously and organically, as humans respond to the provisions nature offers them [18].
Statius’ Silvae and the Villa of Miracles
In the second example, the focus shifts from architecture adapting to nature, to architect and nature actively working together to achieve a complete result. Compared to the Vitruvian example, nature’s role here becomes more active. This example can be found in the first book of the Silvae of the Flavian poet Statius. This might be surprising since a Statian poem (Silvae 4.3) was used earlier to illustrate the ‘default’ situation of hostile nature successfully subdued by the engineer. However, when responding to different challenges, Statius can change his tune. In the poem we are about to consider, nature is cast as very cooperative indeed [19].
In Silvae 1.3, he describes and praises the country villa of a friend, Manlius Vopiscus [20]. Famously, the moral legitimacy of luxurious Roman country retreats was fiercely contested by philosophers, moralists and writers in Rome [21]. A writer wanting to praise a luxurious country villa, therefore, found himself in a difficult position. He had to enter this debate, and address the moralist criticism voiced by other writers. For Statius, one such opponent in the debate is the poet Horace (65-8 BC), who wrote several odes condemning the luxurious villas of Roman nobles, criticizing them for their size, their disrespect of natural boundaries (for example between land and sea) and the use of expensive and unnecessary building materials [22]. Newlands has argued that Statius in his villa poems deliberately evokes Horace as a literary model but answers the strictures against luxurious buildings in various ways [23]. For example, one of the most obvious of Statius’ reactions to Horace is his bold assertion that a villa praised for its gilded beams (35) coloured marbles (36), and an art collection containing everything from bronze sculptures to ivory carving and gems (47-51), provides luxu (…) carentes deliciae (92-3) – “pleasure without luxury”, while all of these features are named by Horace as synonymous with despicable luxury [24].
What Newlands does not note is that not only Horace, but also Seneca, is a formidable literary opponent for Statius. The younger Seneca devoted several of his Epistulae Morales to the topic of suitable living and the dangers of the country villa, as well as raging against excesses of daring and luxurious architecture in general. Again, Statius specifically addresses the points which Seneca puts forward as his strongest arguments against luxury living. One example of this literary response: Seneca argues at length that the luxurious surroundings of his villa encouraged in a man called Vatia not the productive leisure of the philosopher (otium), but inertia, laziness (Ep. 55.3-5). It is no accident that Statius dwells extensively on the particular kind of otium and quies (quiet) enjoyed by Manlius Vopiscus and another friend, Pollius Felix (who features in Silvae 2.2), in their respective retreats and on the ways in which this state is a result of the architectural surroundings: not laziness, but precisely otium conducive to reflection and the writing of poetry [25].
Among the different methods by which Statius counters Seneca and Horace to make a powerful case for the moral acceptability of building luxury villas [26], there is one strategy of particular interest, designed to respond to both Seneca and Horace (among others): his use of the topos of cooperation between man and nature. Both Horace and Seneca stress that builders of luxurious dwellings interfere with natural boundaries (especially between water and land), and that artificiality and technology threaten to disrupt the ‘natural state’ of things. Horace, in the first of his so-called ‘Roman Odes’, depicts the building of a villa into the sea as an illustration of sinful human desire for luxury and stresses the shock it causes to the natural system, focalised through the fish who feel their natural habitat shrink [27].
In Silvae 1.3, on the other hand, nature actively complements the activities of the architect through her own devices (Silvae 1.3.15-23):
How gentle the nature of the ground! What beauty in the blessed spot before art’s handiwork! Nowhere has Nature indulged herself more lavishly. Tall woods brooded over rapid waters. A deceptive image answers the foliage and the reflection flows unchanging in the long stream. Anio himself (what wondrous allegiance!), full of rocks above and below, here rests his swollen rage and foamy din, as though loath to disturb the Pierian days and song-filled slumbers of tranquil Vopiscus. (Translation: Shackleton-Bailey, adapted) [28].
The builder has only to help nature complete what she has already begun. Nature herself has made the site of the villa a luxurious space, and the builder is following nature’s lead in continuing in this luxurious vein [29]. In Silvae 4.3, as we saw above, the river Volturnus first had to be subdued and channeled by force, before he claimed now to flow more happily under human control (4.3.72-84). The river Anio does not offer Vopiscus an opportunity to demonstrate his ability to win the war against nature. In order to render the landscape suitable for Vopiscus’ poetic slumbers, he quietens down of his own accord.
In the first line of this passage, the cooperation between nature and engineer is expressed most clearly. The ground has a gentle ingenium (15) – a clear personification, since ingenium is, in its most basic meaning, that with which man is born, and is only very rarely used of non-human agents [30]. The ingenium of the ground is then complemented by the artes (16) of the engineer. The classic combination of ingenium and ars, both of which the artist needs in order to create a great artefact, is a commonplace in ancient literature [31]. Statius separates the pair and distributes the necessary qualities between nature and the engineer. Only if they cooperate can the villa be truly perfect [32].
The harmony and happy co-existence of cultivation and nature goes to quite extraordinary lengths. It is encapsulated in the exquisitely humorous image of the Anio going for a night-time swim in the clean waters of the nearby aqueduct, the Aqua Marcia (70-74), thereby cleansing the estate’s large-scale water-management (64-7) of its dangerous associations [33]. In lines 59-63, the poet describes that a tree has been preserved in the middle of the house (mediis servata penatibus arbor, 59), which passes through roofs and doorways to emerge into the open sky (tecta per et postes liquidas emergis in auras, 60). This house carries no suggestion of having been won from nature: the rhetoric of war and victory has here been replaced by that of harmonious and fruitful cooperation between architect and nature. One of the main arguments of the moralising critics, that the luxurious villa violates natural boundaries through unnatural excess, has been effectively disproved [34].
Pliny’s Natural History and the Sustainability of Luxury
Pliny the Elder, the author of a huge Natural History in 37 books, describes nature as fundamentally beneficial to mankind [35]. Nature exists to help man and to provide generously for all his needs. However, whilst nature is designed in this beneficial way, man must, according to Pliny, not try to lay his hand on things which nature does not readily provide. Diving into the depth of the sea for pearls, or excavating the earth in mining for precious metals is to take from nature things which she has deliberately withheld from mankind since they are harmful and corrupting [36]. Mining or pearl-diving are therefore sinful activities, driven by luxuria, and contrary to nature [37]. Pliny thus approves of the human use and deployment of all the resources nature readily provides, but not of major human interventions in the ‘natural state’, which are driven by human desire for more than an appropriate share [38].
Keeping Pliny’s general ideas about the relationship between man and nature in mind, let us now consider his treatment of one particular kind of intervention in nature, namely the quarrying (and subsequent use of) marble, discussed in book 36 of the Natural History. The book begins with a diatribe against the use of the luxury material ‘marble’ as such (36.1-5). Quarrying marble is called an insania, madness (36.1), and is condemned for disturbing the natural boundaries of nature (36.1-3):
Mountains, however, nature had made for herself to serve as a kind of framework for holding firmly together the innards of the earth … we quarry these mountains and haul them away for mere pleasure … We should each of us reflect … when we see the masses of marble that are being conveyed or hauled and think how much more happily many people live without them. (translation: Eichholz, adapted) [39]
This diatribe is followed by a long list of things that can be made from marble (and stone more generally): statues, then buildings all over the world, and finally, buildings in Rome. Some, but by no means all of these statues and buildings are described as luxurious and immoral. When Pliny turns to the city of Rome and its miracula, its miraculous features, he finds there, too, a combination of buildings he claims are praiseworthy (such as the Forum of Augustus or the Templum Pacis), and of luxurious abominations (especially the theatres of Scaurus and Curio).
The weakness in Pliny’s logic is obvious. According to his own principles, any building made of marble should be condemned as immoral. But in the case of Rome, he can hardly avoid praising many of the additions to the cityscape, especially those by ‘good’ citizens or emperors. Unfortunately, the buildings he approves of tend to actually be decorated with exactly the same sorts of coloured marbles as those he criticizes [40].
Pliny’s main strategy for protecting in buildings from the charge of luxury is the stress he puts on their usefulness (utilitas), the strategy referred to in the introduction. The clearest example of this is his concluding list of vera aestimatione invicta miracula, miracles unsurpassed in their genuine value (36.121). This list includes the most high-profile engineering achievements of the Roman empire: the aqueducts, harbours, roads, and channels which so convincingly demonstrate Roman supremacy over nature. Despite the huge intervention in nature that they represent, these achievements are clearly praiseworthy in the eyes of any Roman on account of their undisputable utilitas [41].
Another strategy, which provides more general justification for the presence of (partly luxurious) marble architecture in Italy and Rome, is to suggest that these alterations of the natural state are in fact assisted by nature herself. In this way, Pliny can show that the activities comply with his own moral precept of taking from nature only what she provides of her own accord. At the very end of the long section on Roman architecture, Pliny returns very briefly to the quarrying of marble (36.125):
Among the many marvels of Italy itself is one for which the accomplished natural scientist Papirius Fabianus vouches, namely that marble actually grows in its quarries; and the quarrymen, moreover, assert that the sores on the mountainsides fill-up of their own accord. If this is true, there is reason to hope that there will always be marble sufficient to satisfy luxury’s demands. (translation: Eichholz) [42]
This passage picks up the introduction to book 36, where quarrying marble was still roundly condemned. At this stage, it is suggested that nature does, after all, provide marble of her own accord. The anatomical language applied to nature in 36.1 and there employed to stress the violation committed by man in quarrying marble (telluris viscera, the innards of the earth) is picked up and overwritten in this passage. In 36.1, quarrying was condemned for causing irreparable damage: here, the sores (ulcera) of the quarries turn out to heal of their own accord [43]. It remains important that the re-growth of marble only applies to Italy: it is called a marvel of Italy (miraculum Italiae), a natural miraculum to match and justify the many man-made mirabilia and miracula of Rome and Italy [44]. In Italy, at least, nature’s cooperative stance provides some justification for the exploitation of marble. Quarrying marble might not be morally excellent, and it is inextricably connected with luxury, but the ‘sustainability’ (to use a modern term) of its exploitation renders it at least acceptable.
Conclusion
The rhetoric of cooperation between man and nature is, as we have seen, employed in texts ranging from encomiastic poetry to technical and encyclopedic writing, in order to respond to specific challenges and protect large-scale interventions in nature from moral criticism.
On some counts, the rhetoric of Pliny, Statius or Vitruvius seems very modern – the idea of working with nature, not against it, has a distinctly green tinge to it, and it even seems as though Pliny was interested in something like the sustainability of natural resources. But the differences between ancient and modern rhetorics of environmental reassurance are in fact considerable. I conclude with a more general, though tentative, suggestion, which builds on literary analysis for some (speculative) cultural-historical remarks. Our modern-day evaluation of the acceptability of human intervention in nature tends to depend on the actual consequences of these actions. Our anxieties are focused around (actual) sustainability, potential dangers for us or future generations, and the harm and suffering created for other species. The rhetoric used for example by politicians or environmental organisations, and intended to convince us that some project is good or bad, reflects and addresses these anxieties. Roman environmental attitudes differ fundamentally from ours in that respect. Roman texts, too, reveal concerns about interfering with nature on a large scale, but often they are not related to actual dangers or consequences. The concerns activated or allayed by the rhetorical strategy I have focussed on are more abstract: they relate to a general idea that there is such a thing as a ‘natural state’ and natural boundaries, and that crossing them is a moral offense [45]. Where we worry about the consequences of the oil spill in the Gulf of Mexico or the radioactive pollution in the Pacific, it was villas built too far out into the sea that caused ‘environmentally-conscious’ Romans sleepless nights.
Bibliography
Babbitt, F. C. (trans.) (1936) Plutarch’s Moralia: in sixteen volumes. Vol. IV: 263d-351b, Cambridge, London
Beagon, M. (1992) Roman Nature. The Thought of Pliny the Elder, Oxford
---- (1996) “Nature and views of her landscapes in Pliny the Elder”, in: Shipley, G., Salmon J.B. (eds.), Human landscapes classical antiquity: environment and culture, London-New York, 284-309
Brown, F. E. (1963) “Vitruvius and the liberal art of architecture”, Bucknell Review 11.4, 99-107
Callebat, L., Gros, P., Jacquemard, C. (1999) Vitruve, De l’Architecture, Livre II, texte établi et traduit par L. Callebat, introduit et commenté par P. Gros, recherche sur les manuscrits et apparat critique par C. Jacquemard, Paris
Cancik, H. (1978) “Tibur Vopisci”, Boreas 1, 116-34
Carey, S. (2003) Pliny’s Catalogue of Culture: Art and Empire in the Natural History, Oxford
Citroni Marchetti, S. (1982) “Iuvare mortalem. L’ideale programmatico della Naturalis Historia di Plinio nei rapporti con il moralismo stoico-diatribico”, Atene e Roma 27, 124-48
---- (1991) Plinio il Vecchio e la tradizione del moralismo romano, Pisa
Coarelli, F. (1989) “La casa dell’aristocrazia romana secondo Vitruvio”, Munus non ingratum, Geertmann, H., Jong, J.J. de (eds.) BaBesch 178-187
Coleman, K. M. (1988) Statius: Silvae IV, Oxford
Dam, H.-J. van (1984) P. Papinius Statius, Silvae Book II: A Commentary, Leiden
Drerup, H. (1957) Zum Ausstattungsluxus in der römischen Architektur, Münster
Edwards, C. (1993) The Politics of Immorality, Cambridge
---- (1996) Writing Rome, Cambridge
Eichholz, D.E. (1962) Pliny: Natural history. X: Libri XXXVI-XXXVII, Cambridge-London
Fantham, E. (2009) Latin Poets and Italian Gods, Toronto
Fedeli, P. (1990) La natura violata: Ecologia e mondo romano, Palermo
Friedländer, L. (1919) Darstellungen aus der Sittengeschichte Roms, Leipzig
Gale, M.R. (2000) Virgil on the Nature of Things: The Georgics, Lucretius and the Didactic Tradition, Cambridge
Granger, F. (1931-4) Vitruvius on Architecture. 2 vols., Cambridge-London
Gummere, R. M. (1920) Seneca: Epistles 66-92, Cambridge
Hughes, J. D. (1994) Pan’s Travail: Environmental Problems of the Ancient Greeks and Romans, Baltimore-London
Hübner, U. (1985) “Die literarischen und architektonischen Zeugnisse über den vorchristlichen Athos”, Antike Welt 16.1, 35-44.
Kleiner, F.S. (1991) “The trophy on the bridge and the Roman triumph over nature”, L’Antiquité Classique 60, 182-92
Kullmann, W. (2010) Naturgesetz in der Vorstellung der Antike, besonders der Stoa: eine Begriffsuntersuchung, Stuttgart
Mayor, J. E. B. (1878) Thirteen Satires of Juvenal with a Commentary. 2 vols. 2nd ed., London-Cambridge
McEwen, I. K. (2003) Writing the Body of Architecture, Cambridge
Morel, P.-M. (2003) “Technique et nécessité. Le modèle de l’adaptation de Démocrite à Vitruve”, in: Lévy, C., Besnier, B., Gigandet, A. (eds.) Ars et Ratio. Sciences, art et métiers dans la philosophie hellénistique et romaine, Brussels
Newlands, C. (2002) The Poetics of Empire, Cambridge
---- (2011) Statius: Silvae – Book II, Cambridge
Nisbet, R.G.M., Hubbard, M. (1977) A Commentary on Horace: Odes – Book II, Oxford
Pavlovskis, Z. (1973) Man in an Artificial Landscape: The Marvels of Civilisation in Imperial Roman Literature, Leiden
Pearcy, L.T. jr. (1977) “Horace’s Architectural Imagery”, Latomus 36, 772-81
Pitcher, R.A. (1990) “The Emperor and his virtues: the qualities of Domitian”, Antichthon 24, 86-95
Purcell, N. (1987) “Town in Country and Country in Town”, in: MacDougall, E.B, Blair, E. (eds.) Ancient Roman Villa Gardens, Washington D.C., 187-203
---- (1996) “Rome and the management of water: environment, culture and power”, in: Shipley G., Salmon J. (eds.) Human Landscapes in Classical Antiquity: Environment and Culture, London-New York, 180-212
Romano, E. (1994) “Dal de officiis a Vitruvio, da Vitruvio a Orazio: il dibattito sul lusso edilizio”, in: Le Projet de Vitruve: objet, destinataires et réception du ‘De architectura’. Collection de l’École française de Rome 192, Rome, 63-73
Sallmann, K. (1961) “Die Natur bei Lukrez: Natura und der Naturbegriff”. Diss. Cologne University, 1959, Bonn --- (1986): “La responsabilité de l’homme face à la nature”, Helmantica 37, 251-66
Scheithauer, A. (2000) Kaiserliche Bautätigkeit in Rom: Das Echo in der Literatur, Stuttgart Schneider, K. (1995) Villa und Natur: Eine Studie zur römischen Oberschichtkultur im letzten vor- und ersten nachchristlichen Jahrhundert, München
Shackleton Bailey, D. R., (trans.) (2003) Statius: Silvae, Cambridge-London
Smolenaars, J.J.L. (2006) “Ideology and Poetics along the Via Domitiana: Statius’ Silvae 4.3”, in: Nauta, R., Dam, H.-J. van, Smolenaars, J.J.L. (eds.) Flavian Poetry, Mnemosyne Supplement 270, Leiden, 223-44
Spencer, D. (2011) Roman Landscape: Culture and Identity, Cambridge
Thommen, L. (2009) Umweltgeschichte der Antike, Munich
Traina, G. (1988) “Da Dinocrate a Vitruvio”, Civiltà classica e cristiana 9, 303-349
Wallace-Hadrill, A. (1990) “Pliny the Elder and Man’s Unnatural History”, Greece & Rome 37, 80- 96
Weeber, K.-W. (1990) Smog über Attika: Umweltverhalten im Altertum, Zürich
West, D. (2002) Horace: Odes III – Dulce Periculum, Oxford
Whitehorne, J.E.G. (1969) “The Ambitious Builder”, Journal of the Australasian Universities Modern Language Association 31, 28-39
Wilson, A. I. (2008) “Hydraulic Engineering and Water Supply”, in: Oleson, J. P. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Engineering and Technology in the Classical World, Oxford, 285-318
Wray, D. (2007) “Wood. Statius’s Silvae and the Poetics of Genius”, Arethusa 40.2, 127-43
Notes
19. On the combination of rhetoric of cooperation and of domination in Silvae 2.2, see above.
21. See Edwards (1993: 144 ff.), Beagon (1995: 75-9) and Schneider (1992: 105-10).
36. For the most extensive statement of this idea, see Pliny’s condemnation of mining in 33.1-5.
43. These passages also recall the extensive use of anatomical language in 33.1-3.
44. On mirabilia and miracula in the Natural History, see Carey (2003: passim).